When quantum mechanics was first developed, it was formulated in a nonrelativistic limit - the particles involved were presumed not to have enough kinetic energy to create other particles. Because, if they did, then not only the quantum states of each particle, but the number of particles present, would have to be described by the theory. You can see that the combination of quantum mechanics with relativity makes relativistic quantum mechanics a rather more complicated sort of problem.
Quantum mechanical equations were found for bosons (the Klein-Gordon equation) and for fermions (the Dirac equation) which obeyed the correct relativistic transformations, but now the wave functions [ for bosons, for fermions] could not be interpreted as simply as before - in terms of the probability amplitude for a single particle. Now they had to be interpreted as the probability amplitude of the field of the corresponding particle, for which the number of such particles was merely a quantum number of the field.
As a result, when a particle physicist speaks of "the electron," (s)he is referring to the electron field, an absolutely literal example of the Platonic Ideal, in which the disposition (and even the number) of actual individual electrons is merely a state of the electron [field]. An actual single individual particle in the laboratory is rarely the source of much information about the complete set of all its identical siblings.
A given Feynman diagram therefore represents one possible case of the numbers and types of particles present in an interaction with a specified initial and final state. It is one possible manifestation of the fields.